Aristotle substance examples

Biography:Aristotle

Short description: Ancient Greek philosopher and polymath (384–322 BC)

Aristotle

Roman copy (in marble) of a Greek bronze bust of Aristotle by Lysippos (c. 330 BCE), with modern alabaster mantle

Born384 BCE

Stagira, Chalcidian League

Died322 BCE (aged 61–62)

Chalcis, Euboea, Macedonian Empire

EducationPlatonic Academy

Notable work

EraAncient Greek philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
School
Notable studentsAlexander the Great, Theophrastus, Aristoxenus

Main interests

Notable ideas

Aristotelianism

Aristotle (;Greek: ἈριστοτέληςAristotélēs, pronounced [aristotélɛːs]; 384–322 BCE) was an Ancient Greecephilosopher and polymath. His writings cover a broad range of subjects spanning the natural sciences, philosophy, linguistics, economics, politics, psychology and the arts. As the founder of the Peripatetic school of philosophy in the Lyceum in Athens, he began the wider Aristotelian tradition that followed, which set the groundwork for the development of modern scien

Selected Bibliography on Aristotle's Theory of Categorical Syllogism

  • Ackrill, John Lloyd. 1962. "Critical Notice on G. Patzig, Die aristotelische Syllogistik, Gottingen 1959." Mind no. 71:107-117.

  • Andrade-Lotero, Edgar, and Novaes, Catarina Dutilh. 2012. "Validity, the Squeezing Argument and Alternative Semantic Systems: the Case of Aristotelian Syllogistic." Journal of Philosophical Logic no. 41:387-418.

  • Angelelli, Ignacio. 1978. "Analytica priora, I, 38 and Reduplication." Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic no. 19:295-296.

    "Although many commentators have summarized chapter 38 of Analytica Priora I as if it was perfectly clear to them, I have not found their explanations satisfactory enough. In fact, I think Aristotle's text needs badly some sort of clarification that makes it meaningful to modern logicians. In this note I wish to propose one such reconstruction."

  • Austin, John L. 1952. "Critical notice on Łukasiewicz, Aristotle's Syllogistic." Mind no. 61:395-404.

    Withj a correction: Mind, 61, 1952,

    Mereology

    "Mereology" (from Greek meros, "part") is the theory (often formalized) of part, whole, and cognate concepts. The notion of part is almost ubiquitous in domain of application, and for this reason Edmund Husserl assigned its investigation to formal ontology. Aristotle observed that the term part was used in various ways, as for a subquantity, a physical part (leg of an animal), a part in definition (animal is part of man), a part in extension (man is part of animal). Part concepts had obvious applications in geometry and were among Euclid's undefined terms. Several senses of "part" are expressible using the preposition "in," but not all uses of "in" express parthood.

    Until the twentieth century it was generally assumed that the concept of part was sufficiently clear not to require elucidation, but gradually the need for a formal treatment became apparent. Euclid's maxim that the whole is greater than the part appeared to be contradicted by infinite classes, for example. In 1901 Husserl proposed a general theory of part and whole and distinguished several kinds of p

  • Copyright ©momitem.pages.dev 2025